×
welcome covers

Your complimentary articles

You’ve read one of your four complimentary articles for this month.

You can read four articles free per month. To have complete access to the thousands of philosophy articles on this site, please

Science

Reflective Equilibrium

Our philosophical science correspondent Massimo Pigliucci finds himself deep in it.

Suppose you believe in the inerrancy of the Bible. Suppose you also think morality comes from God. Further, suppose you maintain that it is immoral to deliberately kill children. Then you read the following in Exodus 21:17: “He that curseth his father or his mother, shall surely be put to death.” (Something similar also appears in the New Testament: “For God commanded, saying, Honour thy father and mother: and, He that curseth father or mother, let him die the death” – Matthew 15:4.) If you are concerned about the coherence of your beliefs, you now have several moves at your disposal. You could admit that the Bible is not infallible, and that God may not have said what Exodus and Matthew attribute to Him. Or, you could abandon the idea that morality comes from God, and instead turn to the tricky proposition that human beings may decide on their own even whether gods behave immorally. Lastly, you could come to agree that it is alright to kill children who disrespect their elders. In considering any of these options, and adjusting your set of beliefs about morality, divinity and children’s behavior, you have engaged in adjusting what philosophers call your ‘reflective equilibrium’.

The concept (but not the term) was introduced by Nelson Goodman in a classic book published in 1955, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Goodman was not concerned with morality, but rather with the validity of one’s reasoning, both inductive and deductive. Goodman’s suggestion was that we justify our rules of inference based on how those rules fare when compared with a range of instances of what we believe are correct conclusions. In other words, sometimes, if an inferential rule yields unacceptable results, we may decided to discard that rule, no matter how it may have seemed like a good idea beforehand.

The most famous application of the principle of reflective equilibrium (and use of the term) is found in John Rawls’ highly influential A Theory of Justice (1971). Rawls proposed to apply Goodman’s ‘coherentist’ approach to adjusting our sometimes conflicting moral beliefs, just as in the case of the Bible and disrespectful children mentioned above. Whether or not one agrees with the outcome of Rawls’ analysis of justice as fairness, the reflective equilibrium approach should be compelling to anyone seriously interested in, well, reflecting on their own beliefs.

It turns out that a similar approach had already been used in the philosophy of science by Pierre Duhem, as a way to debunk the common idea that science is about the direct empirical testing of theories. In a book published in 1908, La Théorie Physique, Duhem pointed out that if there is a disagreement between a theory and the empirical evidence, one cannot automatically reject the theory, because scientific theories are complex statements which include many ancillary conditions and sub-theories. The existence of a disagreement between theory and evidence tells us that something is wrong, but not what. It could indeed be that the core theory – say, the Copernican idea of a Sun-centered solar system – ought to be rejected. But it could also be that some adjustment to the theory would resolve the discrepancy, for example, Kepler modified Copernicus’ theory to say that the planets go around the Sun following elliptical (ovoid), not circular, orbits. Indeed, it may even be the case that the data is wrong, because of a malfunction in the instrumentation (which was one of the reasonable objections raised by critics of Galileo, since his telescope was largely untested). There could also be an error in the interpretation of data.

Duhem’s thesis was largely unknown in the literature until it was mentioned by W.V.O. Quine in his landmark 1953 paper, ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’. In this paper, Quine extended Duhem’s thesis, arguing that whenever there is a discrepancy in our understanding of the world, to account for the discrepancy one could potentially change any of the interconnected statements that constitute that understanding. Famously, Quine held that even logic itself may have to be altered if it turned out that there were enough problems caused by its application. (Don’t laugh: there is a whole field of ‘paraconsistent logic’ that does exactly that, to account for classical paradoxes like Bertrand Russell’s famous problem concerning sets which are not members of themselves.)

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy summarizes the Duhem-Quine thesis in this fashion: “(i) since empirical statements are interconnected, they cannot be singly disconfirmed; and (ii), if we wish to hold a particular statement true, we can always adjust another statement.” The entry goes on to say that, ironically, Duhem would probably agree with sub-thesis (i) but reject sub-thesis (ii). Be that as it may, both theses together form yet another application of reflective equilibrium – only an equilibrium that is constrained not just by our beliefs, but also by our methods (both scientific and logically-inferential ones), and further, by the way the world happens to be.

The idea of reflective equilibrium is one of the most powerful in philosophy, and indeed embodies a quintessentially philosophical approach to problems of all kinds. The on-going adjustment of one’s views is also applicable in everyday life, of course, and so can be used to introduce non-philosophers to what it means to think philosophically. The crucial thing to remember is that the equilibrium is not meant to be static: new evidence and new ideas constantly enter the system, and a wise person keeps adjusting their beliefs accordingly. Try it, it’s a refreshingly liberating exercise.

© Prof. Massimo Pigliucci 2012

Massimo Pigliucci is Professor of Philosophy at the Graduate Center of the City University of New York. He is the author of Nonsense on Stilts: How to Tell Science from Bunk (University of Chicago Press, 2010). His philosophical musings can be found at: www.rationallyspeaking.org.

This site uses cookies to recognize users and allow us to analyse site usage. By continuing to browse the site with cookies enabled in your browser, you consent to the use of cookies in accordance with our privacy policy. X